Please register or login to continue

Register Login

The One To The Many (Ο Ένας στους Πολλούς)
The One To The Many (Ο Ένας στους Πολλούς)

The One To The Many (Ο Ένας στους Πολλούς)

Franc68Lorient Montaner

-From the Meletic Scrolls.

In Meleticism, the One to the many plays a foundational role in understanding the profound relationship between (To Ένa) the One and the multitude of existential realities that emanate from it. This concept is not merely a metaphysical abstraction; it is the fundamental cornerstone upon which the philosophy of Meleticism structures its interpretation of existence. It explains how the multiplicity of the cosmos with its forms, manifestations and becoming arises from a singular, undivided source. From this singularity the fullness of being emerges, radiating through the emanations that align with both the Logos (the principle of order) and the Nous (the principle of formation).

Essentially, this is the unique realisation of life, a moment of ontological animation witnessed by the cosmos itself. From To Ena the discernible patterns of existence arise and the inherent substance that gives shape to matter and form. It is through To Ena that all things, whether physical, intellectual or metaphysical, find their Meletic genesis. As the primary origin of all that exists or comes into being, To Ena propels existence into plenitude through the overflowing abundance of its own essence. Thus, the many, which is the myriad of existential forms is nothing less than the consequence of an unceasing emanation, the result of an infinite fullness giving birth to the multiplicity of universal existence. These emanations are not mere echoes but manifestations of the original source, each carrying the imprint of the One, woven into the innermost fabric of being.

This dynamic is what Meleticism defines as the One to the many, which is a philosophical recognition that the many are rooted in the One, and that all multiplicity is primarily derivative of a singular ontological reality. To Ena is not simply the beginning, but the highest possible form or dimension of reality. We ascertain this through the realisation that its being is not contingent upon the processes of becoming or the changing flow of multiplicity. Unlike the many, which are subject to flux and decay, To Ena remains immutable, eternal and wholly self-sufficient. Its reality is absolute, not relative. It does not transform, evolve or emerge from something else, for it simply is. In this sense, its dimension may be likened to the matrix of the cosmos, the silent and present field in which all becoming unfolds.

Then it follows that the process can also be reversed conceptually. The One to the many is equally the many from the One. We as conscious beings situated within the multiplicity, perceive existence through the lens of the many. Our senses, our intellect, our experiences all operate within the confines of differentiations. All these differentiations are ultimately contingent upon the One. They owe their being to the overflowing unity of To Ena, which itself is unconditioned and unbounded by cosmic laws. To Ena does not follow the processes of the Logos and Nous, for it precedes them. It is not a product of the cosmos but its essential cause, a state of pure being which cannot become anything else, for to become would imply lack, change or imperfection, none of which can be ascribed to To Ena.

This is what makes To Ena untrammelled by the limitations of the many. Whilst the many are bounded by time, form and finitude, To Ena is limitless. It is, in the truest sense, transcendent. The many would not possess any ontological grounding if not for their origin in the One. Without the One, multiplicity would lack coherence and existence itself would fall into chaos or fragmentation. One might compare this to the geometric analogy of the monad, which is the indivisible point at the centre of a circle. From that single point, all circumference emerges. It is from the monad, indivisible and eternal that multiplicity finds structure. If that central point were to be moved or altered it would no longer serve as the centre; the integrity of the circle would be compromised. So too with To Ena, if it were capable of change or modification, it could not remain the origin of multiplicity. In changing, it would lose its status as the source of all becoming and would itself become part of the process it once initiated. As a consequence, the many would lose their point of reference and descend into a state of stagnation, incapable of progression or transformation.

Existence, therefore, which defines the many, must be anchored to something that links it indelibly with the cosmos, with nature and with reality itself. If this linkage were absent, the many would appear to emerge from disparate and chaotic states of being. However, Meleticism affirms only two fundamental states, which are being and non-being. There are no middle states. To Ena is being itself. It is pure, undivided and absolute. It is that intrinsic being which is reflected, however imperfectly in the many. Therefore, the many are demonstrations of being, never independent of it. Because of this, the One to the many is not just a metaphysical speculation, for it is the ultimate reality that transcends the finite nature of our temporal existence. It is not a posited theory; it is an ontological truth, discoverable not only through reason but through the deeper layers of our consciousness.

One might be tempted to conflate To Ena with the notion of a god. Indeed, to many minds a god seems a fitting substitute for the One. Meleticism draws a careful distinction between the two. A god, no matter how exalted, remains limited as a creator. The fundamental act of creation implies separation from that which is created. A god, defined by function or personality, cannot be the origin of multiplicity in the same way as To Ena, for he is involved in the act of creation, and thus bound by time, intention and action. If such a god were truly whole and perfect within himself, then whatever he created would need to reflect a superior order of being. In many belief systems, god is positioned as distinct from his creation, even as external to existence itself. This view negates his universality. If a god does not participate in existence, can he truly be? For to be is to exist. If he exists, what is the nature of that existence that is parallel to an eternal state of being? If his existence is conditioned to existence in what manner does it manifest? If it is metaphysical, then that state of being must sustain itself with existence. Thus, it cannot be separate from existence.

By contrast, To Ena does not require creation to affirm its being. It simply is. If To Ena did not exist, then being itself would collapse into nonexistence. We see, observe and partake in existence. Therefore, To Ena is. It is the source and the sustenance of all existential phenomena. The many, whether we assume them to be finite or infinite, cannot exist autonomously. They require a ground of being, which is a source from which to emerge and to which they must ultimately return. Much like the central point of the circle, To Ena must remain unmoved for it to retain its role as the origin. If it were subject to movement or changes, it would become indistinguishable from the many and would lose its function as the ontological anchor.

The One to the many is not merely a philosophical proposition; it is the unifying principle of universal existence. It affirms that behind the vast diversity of forms, experiences and realities there remains a single, absolute source, which is unmoving, indivisible and eternally present.

Recommend Write a ReviewReport

Share Tweet Pin Reddit
About The Author
Franc68
Lorient Montaner
About This Story
Audience
All
Posted
9 Apr, 2025
Words
1,260
Read Time
6 mins
Rating
No reviews yet
Views
143

Please login or register to report this story.

More Stories

Please login or register to review this story.